If Good Comics Can Have Good Effects
upon Their Readers,
Why Can’t Bad Comics Have Bad
Effects?
OR, Wasn’t Wertham Right After All?
The
name Fredric Wertham hangs like a pall over the history of comic books,
clouding the horizon of the medium like the long gray day of winter’s
overcast. And it is passing strange
that this single individual should be such a pervasive presence. Wertham ranks with Jack Kirby and Will
Eisner and Harvey Kurtzman and Gil Kane as one of a pantheon that shaped the
history of the medium, changing its direction. But Wertham, unlike these other gods, did not work in the medium; he
neither drew nor wrote for comic books.
As every comics fan knows, Wertham
did his best to destroy comic books.
As every comics fan knows, Wertham’s
1954 book, Seduction of the Innocent, tolled
the death knell for comic books as they then existed. His book and his testimony before the infamous so-called Kefauver
Committee focused public attention on comic books, which brought pressure on
comics publishers, which resulted in the creation of the clean-up Comics Code
Authority, and that eventually caused the untimely demise of the revered EC
comics line and a few others.
That’s what every comics fan
knows. Or thinks he knows. Fact is, however, that other comic book
publishers went under, too. And Wertham
was not the sole cause of their collapse. Television, as a much more exciting entertainment alternative to comic
books, played a large part. The
innocent were seduced, all right: they
were seduced away from comic books.
And the deterioration and
interruption of the means of distributing comic books also played a role.
But Wertham gets most of the credit
in our collective consciousness about the abrupt change of course the comic
book industry made in the mid-1950s. He’s the bogeyman. He was the
scientific guru whose “expert opinion” condemned funnybooks.
In his book and his testimony and in
numerous magazine articles, Wertham brought in his indictment again and
again. Reading comic books is bad for
children, he said. It gives them
unwholesome ideas, turning some kids into criminals and some into sex perverts. But even if reading comic books doesn’t turn
everyone into one or the other, the habit does no good for anyone. We should ban comic books, Wertham urged;
and if we can’t ban them, we should forbid their sale to anyone under fifteen.
Many were alarmed by the ferocity of
his attack and the seeming persuasiveness of his credentials. Syndicated newspaper cartoonists were
particularly edgy. Although comic
strips were not included in Wertham’s indictment, it took very little mental
effort to imagine that his argument would eventually lead him to the
funnies.
Milton Caniff mulled about Wertham’s
crusade, and he once penned the following:
“I sat before a television set and
listened to the old familiar sound of an angry voice, heavy with
middle-European accent, saying, ‘The medium should be abolished.’ The fact that
the speaker was referring to comic books was incidental. He was advocating
doing away with a method of expression in a country where freedom of the press
is guaranteed. . . .
“The howl about the comic books is
rapidly becoming the quickest way to eminence in psychiatry as it is practiced
on the American radio. I don't recall what caused juvenile delinquency in my
day, but I am certain the ‘Young Wild West’ series would have confounded the
mental medics if there had been such around in those less analyzed times. . .
. Someone in the field [of comic books]
got away with showing more flank and more blood than the newspaper strips had
dared display up to that point, and the readers lapped it up to the tune of
plenty of dimes at the newsstands. The next (and quite natural) move of the
retail dealers was to call for more brawn and bosom. The distributors got what
they asked for, and the supply and demand war was on. . . .
“[Returning to the complaint in my
opening sentence,] the well-known psychiatrist reached into the mellow depths
of his European background and offered as his solution to the comic book evil
that they be abolished as a medium. The
old, old technique of the packed-in- tight countries: if you can't bend it,
break it. To make his point, the man wanted to eliminate the device through
which millions of kids see Mickey Mouse even if they don't get to the movies or
read a newspaper. . . .
“In his anger at what he claimed to
be the contributing cause of the majority of juvenile delinquency in the United
States today, the good doctor called for the destruction of the device chosen
by the government during the War as the quickest and most effective means of
educating recruits in all branches of the armed forces. The familiar comic book
was utilized to teach everything from basic training in all phases of military
life to the delicate business of interrogation and identification of prisoners
of war. . . .
“None of the [civilian] comic
magazines have been shoved down the throats of readers. They have remained
popular because they entertained. American kids read what they wish to. If they
choose to spend earned or allowance money for comics, they do so. Lacking cash,
they find a means of swapping to obtain the books they want. This pleasant and
competitive world was denied Japanese and German children. They were told in
positive terms what they should and should not read. Of course, this ukase
prevented juvenile delinquency. But the adult delinquency that threw the world
into war is seldom mentioned when the heavy-voiced Vienna- trained psychiatrist
barks over the free American air that a medium of expression should be
abolished.
“As the doctor on the television
show told of the horrible influence of these Yankee ‘blood hucksters’ on the
children who come to his clinic, I heard a chuckle from a 20-year-old girl
[next to me] watching the screen. This handsome young woman will be a junior at
Bryn Mawr next year, but I recalled her as the same neighbor kid for whom I used
to buy armfuls of comic books when she was house-bound with the sniffles or
some other childhood ailment.
“I asked her if her life had been
ruined by those tools of the devil I had brought to her notice. She replied
that she still retained her passion for Tarzan as portrayed in the cartoons,
but that her instinct for crime had early been cooled by the obvious fact that
in the freezer, the warden could cut off her supply of comic books at his
pleasure.
“That seems to be my point.”
But Wertham was not, actually, a
malevolent monster. He was a concerned
psychiatrist. He, like scores of other
Americans at the time, was concerned about a new phenomenon in our national
life. Juvenile delinquency. The increasing criminal inclinations of
America’s youth in the years after World War II alarmed everyone. And everyone looked for causes.
The obvious cause--the erosion of
the influence of the nuclear family due to the absence from the home of fathers
(who were in foreign climes serving in the military during WWII) and of mothers
(who went to work in defense plants and other places to take the places of the
absent male population)--was seldom remarked upon. To blame juvenile delinquency on the failure of the family was
like blaming yourself; and most of us are quicker to blame some other entity
than ourselves. It’s a human failing,
but it’s a failing.
Wertham’s motives in attacking comic
books were entirely laudatory. As Amy
Kiste Nyberg points out in her book, Seal
of Approval: The History of the Comics Code, Wertham’s “call for a ban on
the sale of comic books to children was his way of trying to make a difference
in a society that he saw as hostile to the healthy mental development of
children.”
In her book (University Press of
Mississippi, 1998; $18 in paper), Nyberg traces the events that led to the
establishment of the Code. To set the
stage, she dips as far back into the past as Congress’s passing in 1873 of the
“first comprehensive obscenity law”--known as the Comstock Act because of the
influence of an early crusader for decency, the notoriously self-righteous
Anthony Comstock. She then points out
that newspaper comics came in for criticism very early as being “vulgar”
because they depicted uneducated immigrant children (like the Yellow Kid and his
cohorts).
And criticism of comic books arrived
so hard on the heels of the medium’s advent as to be nearly immediate. Their precursors in the 19th century, dime
novels retailing exotic adventure to American youth, had been roundly
condemned, and comic books were seen as a continuation of the same tradition in
lurid literature for the young.
Nyberg provides a blow-by-blow
history of New York’s attempts to install laws that outlawed comic books
(mostly vetoed by Governor Thomas Dewey as unconstitutional), discusses the
formation of and charge to the U.S. Senate Subcommittee on Juvenile
Delinquency, rehearses key testimony before the subcommittee in the spring of
1954, outlines Wertham’s career both before and after the publication of Seduction, describes the inauguration of
the Code and its consequences, and sketches the Code’s evolution over the last
four decades. The book concludes with
appendices that give all three versions of the Code--1954, 1971, and 1989--and
an extensive bibliography.
For the most part, this is an
objective, noninflammatory recitation of the history of comic book
censorship. Nyberg also makes several
astute observations (observations doubtless made before but often overlooked in
such histories as this).
Perhaps the most insidious effect of
the Code, she points out, is to define the audience for comic books as very
nearly exclusively children. This, of
course, did more to stunt the possible evolution of the artform than any other
single circumstance.
She also observes that the Code was
almost always imagined by those who conceived it as mostly window-dressing, a
public relations ploy that would allow the critics to think they’d won but
would permit the comic book industry to make as few concessions to them as
possible (which, ironically, supports Wertham’s contention about the venal
motives of comic book publishers).
But the plan did not work out quite
the way the cynical publishers imagined it would. The first administrator of the Code, Judge Charles E. Murphy,
took his assignment much more seriously than the publishers thought he
would. He actually succeeded in forcing
adherence to the Code.
As for EC Comics’ departure from the
field--according to Nyberg, driving EC out of business was seen by most comic
book publishers as good for the industry. EC was the sacrificial lamb, proving that the industry was serious about
cleaning up its act. Moreover, EC’s
exit (and that of a couple of other minor publishers) was also good business:
it reduced the number of comic books on the stands and thereby improved the
chances of survival for other publishers.
Nyberg also frames criticism of
comic books in a larger context. The
issue, she says, was who was to control the education of children. The conflict was between the cultural elite
and popular culture.
In this struggle, the scientific
accuracy of the allegations against comic books was beside the point. Even though most research findings
contemporary with Wertham’s so-called study suggested that the critics greatly
exaggerated the ill effects of reading comics--that, in fact, most of the
assumptions held about the negative influence of comics were not valid--that
didn’t matter. Nor did it matter that
reading comic books actually had some value in an educational mode.
Nyberg admits that Wertham’s book
was not a very scientific indictment of comic books. Social scientists today, she says, fault the book for its lack of
scientific methodology.
“They conclude that Wertham’s book
proposed a simplistic model of ‘direct and immediate relation between cause and
effect. . .’” and that “his criticism was a ‘crude social learning theory model
which either implicitly or explicitly assumed unmediated modeling effects,
often accompanied by an equally simple Freudian interpretation of comic
content.’”
But these critics miss the point,
Nyberg says. Wertham never intended his
book to be a scholarly report on research. Although based upon his research, the book was conceived as a propaganda
vehicle, a sensational screed by which he hoped to mobilize public opinion
against comic books. In short, the book
was concocted out of political not scientific motives. And by linking juvenile delinquency to comic
book reading, Wertham provoked action.
Although we may believe that he
succeeded in his purpose, Wertham himself thought he had failed. He correctly saw that the Code was merely a
ruse and that it could not accomplish what outlawing comics altogether would
accomplish--purifying the environment in which children were growing up.
Wertham was one of the first (or, at
least, one of the most conspicuous of the social science pioneers) to assert
that environment shaped personality. And he was also among the first to assert that violence in mass media,
whether as news or as entertainment, conditions us to accept violence. And as we become more tolerant of it, more
of it occurs.
Nyberg applauds Wertham’s
motives--at times, almost as if she supposes that good intentions are
sufficient justification for faulty science. The clinical method of Wertham’s science may, in fact, be valid in
certain situations (as many today assert), but the sample from which
conclusions are drawn must be broader and more varied than Wertham’s interviews
with children who, for one reason or another, found themselves in a psychiatric
clinic in Harlem.
Although Nyberg diligently (and
rightly) aims to destroy the malevolent bogeyman version of Wertham by
rehearsing his professional achievements, the fact that his criticism of comic
books belongs within his larger concern about the effects of media is not
evidence that his scientific method was not naive.
Even if Wertham were a better
scientist than the content of the book suggests, the book itself exists as a
tract purporting to be scientific and as such is an example of deeply flawed
attitudes about the scientific method.
Seduction
of the Innocent is a bubbling stew of accusation and innuendo, a grab-bag
of isolated instances, fragmentary case histories, insinuating near-facts, and
innumerable anecdotes that retail as cause-and-effect relationships a host of
happenings whose only connection with each other is sequential. More forensic than scientific, the book
attains a modest stature only as literary criticism.
The scientific foundation upon which
Wertham builds his indictment seems a trifle shaky if judged by present-day
research standards. He presents no
statistical analysis of his data, for instance--nothing that reports how many
subjects he interviewed and what percentage of them became juvenile delinquents
because of their comic book reading. There is no precise analysis of the population he studied: how many were
juvenile delinquents, how many were not? None of Wertham’s conclusions were ever subjected to experimental
validation. Although such an experiment
would doubtless prove impossible to implement, his findings might acquire
greater validity if he had studied a “normal” comic book reading population and
compared the results to those that emerged from his study of children who had
come to his mental hygiene clinic in Harlem for consultation or treatment of
some behavioral problem.
As an example of the sort of
rhetoric Wertham employs, consider this assessment of children’s “violent
games”--games of cops and robbers, cowboys and Indians.
Wertham allows that “violent games
may be harmless enough, but only a hairline divides them from the acts of petty
vandalism and destructiveness which have so increased in recent years.”
What he says may be true: “only a
hairline divides . . . .” They are,
indeed, separate acts. But notice how
he implies a cause-and-effect relationship between two sets of facts without
actually saying one causes the other.
Assuming for the nonce that he has
successfully demonstrated a causal relationship between comic book reading and
violent games, he pairs this “fact” with another--an increase in petty
vandalism--implying that playing violent games leads directly to committing
petty vandalism.
Wertham frequently employs this kind
of rhetoric, and its sloppy logic that slyly indicts by association only
weakens his argument over-all by making him appear less that straight-forward
in the presentation of his case.
The good doctor was driven to this
sort of verbal and intellectual gymnastics because he was unable to prove the
truth of his allegations. He failed to
find in a cause-and-effect relationship a connection between reading comic
books and criminal or aberrant behavior in young readers.
Ironically, he actually cites an
instance that contradicts his thesis--without apparently realizing it. It is one of the few instances of his
drawing upon a case not originating in a clinical setting.
In a study conducted with 355
children of better-than-average-income families who were enrolled in a
parochial school “where ethical teaching played a large part” in lessons,
children read both comics of the “better sort” and “bad” (i.e., crime)
comics. Astonishingly, the children
recognize the flaws in the comic book stories. Superman is “bad” because he is portrayed as a god. Some comic books are bad but fun to
read. Some will lead readers into
sinning.
The kids found examples of “impure
thoughts,” “indecency,” and the like.
Anyone concerned about the
corrupting influence of comic books should derive some comfort from such
remarks. They reveal that the ethical
teaching of the school “took”: it shaped children’s responses to the world
around them. The kids recognized that
some comics were “bad.”
These kids were scarcely
“seduced.” They are, in fact, doing
precisely what their teachers and parents presumably hoped they would do: they
are rejecting the immoral blandishments they encounter.
But Wertham, in failing to remark
upon this circumstance, seems curiously blind to a study that contradicts his
message.
If the book fails in its science, it
almost succeeds as literary criticism.
Crime comic books of the time told
stories about criminals. Typically, the
stories traced the careers of gangsters, beginning with their rise to power in
the underworld and continuing with accounts of their exercise of power and
concluding, eventually, in their downfall. By way of characterizing the demented personalities of the criminals,
most crooks were portrayed as wholly unsavory villains--cruel, thoughtless, and
treacherous, given to acts of merciless brutality and, often, of craven
cowardice.
But the choice of narrative focus
was unfortunate. Concentrating on the
criminal’s career made the criminal the center of the action. The criminal became the protagonist of the
stories and the police the antagonists. In our usual engagement with fiction, protagonists are the “heroes” of
the tale. The narrative configuration
of the stories in crime comics, then, had the rhetorical effect of making
heroes of the crooks. Heroes are
usually admirable, worthy of emulation. Thus, criminals become role models.
Even if the crook is caught or
killed in the end, most of the story is devoted to his success rather than his
failure. Only the last two or three
panels in the story depict the criminal’s undoing. Given this rhetorical weighting, the lesson a young reader might
absorb is not that “crime does not pay.” To suppose, Wertham says, that the final defeat of the villain cancels
out his previous triumphs and achievements is “psychologically naive.”
The lesson, he goes on, “is not that
the villain should have been a better person but that he should have been
shrewder.” His dessert was just because
he was stupid enough to get caught--not because he was evil. The real crime is in getting caught.
Crime comic books (and other mass
media), Wertham says, “make children confuse violence with strength, sadism
with sex, low necklines with femininity, racial prejudice with patriotism, and
crime with heroism.”
To complete the indictment, Wertham
asserts that all comic books are crime comic books. In effect, any comic book in which a story contains some sort of
conflict is a crime comic book.
Not everyone agreed with Wertham
that comic books could cause criminal behavior or that comic books should be
banned.
Bill Gaines, publisher of EC Comics,
for instance. In testimony before the
infamous so-called Kefauver Committee investigating comic books, he said that
he thought comic books were mostly harmless juvenile entertainment.
Others who defended comic books
often cited what they termed the “educational value” of comics. In the much maligned crime comics, the
criminals were always caught and punished. The lesson was that “crime doesn’t
pay.” Thus, comics taught moral values:
good triumphs over evil, law and order over lawlessness, and so on. The lesson was particularly evident in
superhero comic books, the apologists might say: in those, there was absolutely
no question that the bad guys were bad and the good guys were good. The good guys wore tights and fought crime. The formula emphasized the equation: the
values of the good guys were good values.
But this argument is hoist with its
own petard. If comics can teach, then
they can teach both good and bad lessons. If “good comics” teach good behavior, we must assume that “bad comics”
teach bad behavior. If the first
proposition is true, then so is the second.
Or so it would seem.
Those who pooh-poohed Wertham’s
thesis back in the 1950s when it burst fresh upon the horizon steered clear of
this pitfall by using the Predisposition Argument. Crime comics would not lead youthful readers into a life of
crime, the argument went, unless those readers were already somehow predisposed
to commit crimes. Normal kids, the
reasoning ran, would not be affected by tales of criminality or ghoulish
horror. And that, I think, is exactly
the case although there is scarcely any replicable scientific experimental data
upon which to base this conclusion.
There is, however, a logical
basis--the logic of literary criticism.
The issues surrounding Wertham’s
contention have become more insistent over the years, and the social crisis
more urgent. We now have teenagers who
turn their high schools into battlefields and blast away at each other with
arsenals of sophisticated weaponry. Are
these young monsters trained by television and movies just as their
grandfathers might be presumed to have gone to crime school in comic
books?
Wertham’s book, as Nyberg has
demonstrated, was but the tip of the iceberg of his thinking on the subject. In its largest context, Wertham’s theorizing
embraced precisely the concerns that this country has been wrestling with ever
since. He believed that personality was
shaped by environment. Consequently,
violence in society makes violent members of that society. Even more insidiously, violence in our
entertainments conditions us to accept violence everywhere.
Most of us would agree, I believe,
that violence in our entertainments is not altogether healthy. But most of us would also be suspicious of
any theory that suggests that violence on television is the only cause of
violence on the streets and in the schools. There are other contributing factors (as even Wertham admitted,
providing himself with a hedge against the charge that his book made the cause-and-effect
linkage too directly for accurate science). We can find some inkling of what those other factors might be, I submit,
by examining the Predisposition Argument in terms of literary criticism.
One of the tenets of literary theory
is that readers participate vicariously in the lives of those they read
about. The characters in a novel may be
fictional, but if they are convincingly drawn, readers will emphathize with
them and share their dreams and their fears, their agonies and their
victories.
If we didn’t somehow enter
emotionally into these fictional lives, then there would be no suspense in any
work of fiction. We might be curious
about an outcome in the same way that we might be interested in the solution to
a puzzle. The engagement is largely
intellectual rather than emotional.
If the engagement is emotional as
well as intellectual, then we care about the fictional people in somewhat the
same way as we care about our real acquaintances, family, and friends. And only if we care about these make-believe
personages do we care about what happens to them. Only if we care about their well being can the authors of these
fictions keep us in suspense, dangling the question of how it will end before
us throughout the work.
If we feel suspense, then, we may
safely assume we are emotionally engaged with a work of fiction.
Our vicarious involvement with
fictional personages that we regard as real is a humanizing experience: it is
broadening. Reading fiction broadens us
as people because we get to know and understand and sympathize with these other
“people” we encounter in fiction. It
works the same as knowing real people does: the experience widens our internal
horizon of understanding. We are better
for it, more humane, because we are no longer just single, individual,
self-centered egos but, to the degree that we have absorbed the aspirations and
heartaches of others, we have become them, incorporated them within us. By so doing, we become more than just
ourselves: we become them, too. And so
we are better members of humankind because we understand our
commonalities. “Them” becomes “us,” and
we are sympathetic rather than antagonistic.
It is possible to know well more
people through fiction than we can ever know well in real life. It is possible to understand their motives
and emotions better than we can understand real people of our
acquaintance. Between most of us in
real life hangs an opaque veil of self-preserving privacy, and we seldom get
entirely beyond that veil. But we can--and
do--pierce through the opacity in works of fiction, and we get to know more
people and to know them better. And so
reading widely in fiction is a good thing to do if we want to understand the
human condition and embrace the family of humankind.
If something like this isn’t a
reasonable description of what happens between a reader and the work of fiction
he or she is reading, then literature--belle lettres, the entire edifice of
storytelling--cannot function and would not exist.
By what means, then, does an author
create the “emotional engagement” of readers that is at the heart of the
literary experience? The key phrase
several paragraphs ago is “convincingly drawn.” Readers must be persuaded that the fictional folk they encounter
are, for whatever purpose, “real.” In
the famous phrase, we then “willingly suspend disbelief.” We know the work is make-believe, but we
pretend to ourselves that it is real. We do it in order to be entertained, and we are entertained by being
engaged, involved, in the lives of these fictions.
To the extent that a fictional
character seems in various crucial ways to be like us, that character will seem
real to us. If these characters are not
like us, we won’t believe in them--we won’t think they are real. If a character seems to laugh and cry and
aspire for reasons we recognize as similar to our own reasons for laughing or
crying or aspiring, then that character will seem like us and therefore real to
us. If this character lives in a milieu
that is familiar to us--or similar to our own--populated by other characters
whose emotional and mental make-ups are recognizably human, the implicit
argument for believing in the character and the rest of the cast is
enhanced.
On the other hand, if fictional
characters do not seem to react in the ways our lives have taught us that
people react--emotionally, intellectually--to the stimuli of their environment,
then we won’t believe they are real. If
their milieu is peculiar or wholly unfamiliar to us--unrecognizable as a human
milieu--then our willingness to suspend disbelief is further undermined.
If we do not believe in the
characters, we will not enter vicariously into their lives. And if we are not living vicariously in the
pages of that fiction, we will not be affected much by what we encounter there.
And so to a young comic book reader
of the 1950s who lives among the well-tended lawns of American suburbia, the
milieu in crime comic books will seem exotic and fascinating--but not very
familiar. The characters may have recognizable
emotional reactions, but they still live differently and operate strangely in a
strange environment. And they do things
wholly foreign to someone living in the material and emotional comfort of
Eisenhower’s suburbia.
Comparatively speaking.
Compared to comic book readers who
live on the mean streets in large metropolitan areas, that is. Youths who are not secure in either material
or emotional comforts. Young readers
for whom life is a much more desperate struggle to survive than it is for those
who live the well-tended lawn life. For
kids in the inner city, no doubt the fictional world in crime comic books is
not foreign but familiar. These readers
willingly suspend disbelief and live vicariously the lives played out in
four-color fiction before them. And
these readers--as Wertham discovered by interviewing so many of them in the
Lafarge Clinic in New York’s Harlem--might well imitate the actions portrayed
in crime comic books.
Yes, this is the old Predisposition
Argument. And I realize that I’m
simplifying a complex situation, but I do so to dramatize the point: these young readers are not so much
“predisposed” as they are emotionally engaged by fictions that seem, to them,
convincingly accurate portrayals of life as the readers know it. Living vicariously the criminal lives played
out in comics, these readers might well start living real lives of crime
because comic books and their own real milieu have demonstrated persuasively
that criminal activity is the way to survive.
Here, then, is at least one of the
“contributing factors” that Wertham doubtless knew existed--the real
environment of comic book readers. When
the actual parallels the fiction, then there is little difference between
vicarious experience and real experience. And so the former impinges upon, affects, the latter.
For those young readers in
Eisenhower’s suburbia, however, the lives they saw depicted in crime comic book
fictions did not seem real enough, not actual reality at all. And so these readers did not enter into
those fictional experiences as deeply as did their youthful counterparts in the
inner cities. The influence of crime
comics under these circumstances is likely to be entirely negligible. “Harmless,” as Bill Gaines said.
Consider that classic tableau
outside a movie theater after a cops-and-robbers movie has ended and the
audience is leaving: imagine in the
crowd a group of youngsters who swagger out in imitation of one of the more
impressive of the crooks they’ve just seen on the screen. A commonplace scenario. We’ve all seen it. Or enacted it ourselves. Swept up in the ambiance of the flick, we “act out” the part of our
favorite on-screen character.
My contention is that if those kids
are suburban juveniles, they’ll quickly begin laughing at their own
imitations. They do so because those
counterfeit personages are not real to the youths. They are therefore comical.
But if that scene takes place
outside a movie theater in a less manicured neighborhood of an inner city, I
can’t imagine much laughter. Here, that
bullying swagger is not comical. The
kids here see that swagger everyday on the streets, and the movie has simply
provided them with another model to imitate.
In the first instance, the laughter
persuades the youths to give up the imitation; in the second instance, where
there is no derisive laughter, the youths continue the imitation and enlarge,
perhaps, upon it in their actual lives.
And in a similar fashion, “bad
comics” might, under certain circumstances, have a bad influence on their
readers. By the same token, “good
comics” might not have the desired effect.
For readers on the mean streets, the
moral values in “good comics” have comparatively little reality. Those values animate no one these readers
know. Or, more likely, too few of their
acquaintance. And so these comics do
not effect behavior on the mean streets. They are as unrecognizable and foreign and completely strange as crime
comics seem to suburb dwellers. And if
“bad comics” have no effect on suburban juveniles, “good comics,” for the same
reasons, have no effect on urban juveniles.
But “good comics” do affect those
readers whose milieu and values are reflected in the fictions. To suburban readers, these values are
recognizable. And they seem to have validity:
they appear to be working in the readers’ surroundings. And so these readers have their values
reinforced by their comic book reading--just as inner city readers have their
values reinforced by reading “bad comics.”
And that, it seems to me, is why “good
comics” can have good effects and “bad comics” may have no effect at all. By the same token, “bad comics” can have bad
effects and “good comics” no effect at all. It depends upon the extent to which readers are drawn into the fictions
and live vicariously there. It depends,
in other words, upon whether a reader recognizes “his” world in the fiction; if
he does, he will be affected by what he reads. If he doesn’t, he will not.
Again, I recognize that I’m
oversimplifying. But I do it to clarify
the issues in the argument. And if this
argument--the argument of literary criticism--is valid, then it can apply to
other entertainments. Comic books are
no longer as pervasive in the lives of American youth as they were in the late
1940s and early 1950s. They no longer
constitute the threat to social stability that they were once imagined to
be. Other entertainments have taken
their place.
But just as comic books by
themselves “in isolation” could not affect behavior then--just as there are
“contributing” factors present--so are there contributing factors today. Only when there are certain other
contributing factors present can violence in entertainments influence actual
behavior. Alas, we don’t know, exactly,
what those other contributing factors might be. Not with certainty.
But we may be reasonably secure in
supposing that environment--the actual milieu of American youth--has something
to do with it. Family, school,
neighborhood. These are the elements of
milieu. And how are these different
today from what they may have been in, say, the 1930s?--when there was, so we
suppose, less of the kind of violent behavior that we have today.
Families had mothers at home. Daily behavior was therefore under constant
scrutiny. Schools were smaller. Kids felt less anonymous, less lost in huge
crowds. Neighborhoods were more likely
stable: people didn’t come and go as much, so you were a known personage
growing up: the neighbors knew you--and, more importantly, they knew your
mother and father and could report your misbehaviors, if any, to them.
I’m not suggesting that we must
return to yesteryear. I’m not
advocating that mothers must stay in the home. I’m not saying we should reduce the size of educational plants, giving
up the economies that size engenders, the varieties of educational
opportunities ditto. But we haven’t yet
found authentic substitutes for these factors in American life.
Nothing has yet taken the place of
mothers in the home when kids are growing up; nothing has taken the place of the
smaller school which nurtures a sense of self. Nothing has taken the place of the interconnectedness of neighborhoods
in which residents are more or less permanent.
Nothing but television.
Not only is American life different
by reason of changes in family, school, and neighborhood. We also have television. It’s the new kid on the block. (See how quaint that expression sounds? How unaccustomed we are to thinking about
“our block” in the neighborhood?)
TV cannot take the place of family,
school, and neighborhood, but it does fill the void created by changes in those
areas. And it fills that void with
ambiguity. The sensations retailed on
trash talk TV in the late afternoon paint a distorted picture of real life for
young latch-key viewers who absorb impressions undiluted by contradictory
counsel from companionable adults.
Wertham’s over-arching theme--that
environment influences behavior--is surely worth considering. Indeed, it cannot be discounted.
Environmental factors today include
the actual worlds that young people operate in as well as the fictional ones
they encounter in their entertainments. And in those actual worlds, young people are often left too much to
their own devices. Their values are
reinforced by the values of other young people, all living in the moral
ambiguity that is created in the new milieu.
Into the vacuum sweep the schools,
but only for a few disjointed hours a day, leapfrogging from science and math
to English and phys ed. In such a
fragmented environment, where can we find moral constancy? Where is the moral guidance when various
elements of the environment contradict each other? The violence of movies contradicts the lectures of teachers and
the sermons of preachers. Who is right?
Wertham’s science was lousy, but he
was asking the right questions. And the
questions persist. They nag us
today. If we are very lucky, we’ll find
answers untainted by the rhetorical frenzy that animated Wertham’s infamous
tract.
If Wertham taught us anything, he
taught us that political maneuvers inspire only political solutions as shallow
as the politics that motivate them. The politics of appearances affect only
appearances. His book was a political
screed, a pubic relations campaign; the solution to the problems he pronounced--the
Comics Code--was a political solution, another piece of p.r. It changed comic books--a little and for a
while--but it didn’t change any of the other “contributing factors.”
Let’s hope we don’t make the same
mistake again.
Return to Harv's Hindsights |